Blog Archive

Wednesday, November 13, 2024

An Environmental Baseline: Summary and Review of Chapter 4 of Eco-pragmatism by Daniel A. Farber (1999, University of Chicago Press, pgs. 93-132)


     In this chapter, Farber first states that feasibility is the first and main criterion for deciding whether an environmental protection goal is achievable. Determining feasibility involves determining economic feasibility. If the costs of environmental protection exceed the benefits, then that is a recipe for disaster. First, feasibility, then cost-benefit analysis. While cost-benefit analysis may be a mechanical means to making the inevitable tradeoffs of environmental analysis, it is often inadequate by itself. It is better as a secondary approach to back-up feasibility analysis.

     Legal scholar Cass Sunstein has been a proponent and expert on cost-benefit analysis since the 90s. I have read some of his fascinating work in this area. Sunstein pioneered the use of cost-benefit analysis, noting that it was not just useful in situations addressing market failures, but that it could be useful for any environmental policy analysis, and it should be required by government regulators, which it now is. However, cost-benefit analysis is not complete by itself.

 

There are too many judgment calls and too many unquantified factors in environmental problems.”

 

Those unquantified factors must also play a role. Sunstein believes that public values should trump private preferences in environmental policy analysis. Where market failures are the main concern, cost-benefit analysis can be done on purely economic terms, but where risks are inequitably distributed, such as in cases where certain groups of people bear more environmental harm burdens, or in environmental justice issues, economic analysis alone will not suffice. Where to start is an important consideration. This involves a presumptive environmental baseline. Farber writes:

 

The commitments now embedded in federal law generally take an environmentalist baseline, with a presumption in favor of environmental protection. Sunstein would abandon this baseline for a more detached stance. The result would be to designate economic efficiency as the presumptive outcome, shifting the burden to those who advocate other values.”

 

Farber disagrees with Sunstein’s argument in favor of neutrality, arguing instead that counting the interests of polluters and those who bear the burdens of pollution equally does not remove value judgments as intended, but is rather a value judgment itself. Farber argues that the choice of a neutral baseline is dependent on cost-benefit analysis, which itself is dependent on willingness to pay (WTP). However, how much someone is willing to pay for environmental protection is not the only criteria available. There is also a willingness to accept (WTA). Studies have shown that there is often a big difference between willingness to pay and willingness to accept. According to studies, people are willing to accept double what they are willing to pay. Farber quotes a 1990 paper by Jack Knetsch:

 

Asking people to accept payment for a degradation in the quantity or quality of a public good simply does not work in a contingent valuation survey under many conditions, yet substituting a WTP format where theory specifies a WTA format may grossly bias the findings.”

 

Farber argues that using WTP is basically equivalent to making a baseline that favors economic efficiency over environmental protection.

 

 

 

Environmental Baseline Choices

 

     Farber gives three choices of a baseline: common law, which gives the regulated party presumptive entitlement and is often equivalent to the pre-regulation status quo, neutrality, in which no presumptive entitlements are allotted, and a baseline based on the beneficiaries of potential regulation. Sunstein pointed out that common law is often unworkable. In terms of air and water pollution control, the dangers of carcinogens, and hazardous waste, the third baseline, that of the beneficiaries of environmental protection, has been the favored choice. Farber refers to this as an environmentalist baseline. He presents the usual arguments as an environmentalist regulatory approach vs. a libertarian deregulatory approach. While a neutral baseline may be appealing because it gives no advantages, it does not consider our rights to environmental protection to be more important than a company’s right to put those rights into question by polluting at certain levels.

     Farber calls the neutral baseline a fallacy. He gives the environmental law example of Boomer vs. Atlantic Cement Company, a 1970 New York decision, where a cement company, in conjunction with a nearby existing quarry, was built near residences. It is a nuisance law case that involves property rights as well. It is a very well-known case in American legal education. The residents complained about the effects of cracks in their houses from blasting at the quarry and the fine dust that would coat everything in its path and breathing it was probably not good as well. The concrete plant and quarry, however, were major employers in the area so they had beneficial economic effects on the region. The outcome was that the plant stayed open, and the people affected were generously compensated for the damage. The company had acquired the land in secret so there was no way for those stakeholders affected by the pollution to be involved in the hearing process. That is something that is not likely to happen in current times. Farber notes:

 

To adopt a neutral baseline is not itself a neutral decision; it is based on a value judgment of symmetry between polluters and victims.”

 

     Farber advocates for a hybrid of cost-benefit analysis and feasibility analysis for defining a baseline. The cost-benefit analysis part favors an environmental baseline, which has been the default in many cases. The feasibility analysis provides a “reality check” of the cost-benefit analysis. Farber thinks that feasibility analysis does need some constraints to be most effective and that cost-benefit analysis should be used as a benchmark to determine what is feasible. It should not be too open-ended. Feasibility should ideally be practical and sensible.   

 

 

 

The Case for a Hybrid Approach of Cost-Benefit and Feasibility Analyses

 

     Environmentalists have not been fond of cost-benefit analysis, arguing that economic benefits should be weighted lower than environmental impacts. That is likely a useful argument in some cases but not in others. Cost-benefit analysis has been criticized for treating human lives as commodities. However, that is really the only way to quantify costs and benefits in a reasonably consistent manner. We have economic standards, and we have environmental standards. There is the market and there is the environment. Their interrelationships are only partially quantifiable and this limits the effectiveness of cost-benefit analysis. The uncertainty of assigning values often remains. Farber argues that we simply can’t reduce these issues to purely economic terms. Assigning values is equivalent to making judgment calls.

 

If cost-benefit analysis is attacked for cold-bloodedness, feasibility analysis is often considered soft-headed and wedded to foolishly expensive methods of controlling environmental problems. Feasibility analysis is often attacked for requiring inefficient “command-and-control” regulations, in which the EPA directs particular firms to achieve the specific level of pollution control it considers feasible.”

 

The hybrid approach of cost-benefit and feasibility analysis should not be conflated with “command-and-control” methods that often over-regulate, he notes. This is simply an acknowledgment that economic feasibility, not just technological feasibility, should be a major part of feasibility analysis. Again, he notes that cost-benefit analysis by itself is limited. Combining the two in a hybrid approach is equivalent to a pragmatic approach. Both methods of analysis have particular merits. Cost-benefit analysis can be more easily standardized by carrying over assigned values from one case to another. Feasibility analysis has the advantage of being more useful in situations where the data is messy or scant and where social values are less easily quantified. Combining the approaches may to some extent guard against the pitfalls of each individual approach. Each approach makes value choices. The cost-benefit approach utilizes discount rates and valuation problems. These can be difficult to understand for those not used to evaluating problems in such a way. The hybrid approach adds in more understandable metrics like significant risk, feasibility, and gross disproportionality. The case against using cost-benefit analysis alone is simply that we can’t leave environmental decisions to economists alone. Thus, he notes that cost-benefit analysis should assist rather than control regulatory decisions. It can provide a check on unreasonable regulation but it should not be the sole basis for the decision process.

 

It {cost-benefit analysis} functions best as a critical resource to prevent misguided decisions, rather than as an effort to make hard social decisions on spreadsheets.”

 

     Judges and the courts are also guided by interpretations, often canonical, of the legislative intent of statutes like the Clean Water Act and the Clean Air Act. Interpreting ambiguous statutes has been a point of argument for decades. The recent reversal of the so-called Chevron Deference, while widely panned by environmentalists for shifting deference in ambiguous cases away from regulating agencies to Congress and the courts, will likely still defer to the expertise of the agencies in most cases. It is not likely to change legal interpretations when judges make decisions, although in cases of the political ideological makeup of judges, those with the most judges and cases and in the case of SCOTUS, the current conservative majority, will have more influence to interpret as they see fit. Judges are not experts in environmental science, so they are not expected to overrule those who are, at least in most cases. In the case of Congress, it is that body that has the final say and the power of rulemaking. Supporters of the recent SCOTUS decision say that it puts the power of decision-making back where it should be, namely Congress, but also the courts, and takes it away from agency expertise. But it should not be forgotten that this is to be applied only where ambiguity is well-acknowledged.

     Farber notes that his hybrid approach is really at play in most current regulations (1999). He also notes that Congress often backslides on regulations by allowing extensions and variances. He says that is equivalent to slipping feasibility through the back door. He also quips that environmental policy has had an orientation that was too static and not dynamic enough. His principle for risk management is as follows:

 

To the extent feasible without incurring costs grossly disproportionate to any benefit, the government should eliminate significant environmental risks

 

That is a great, if necessarily vague, way to put it, and the bottom line of the chapter and this summary and review, I think.  

No comments:

Post a Comment

     The SCORE Consortium is a group of U.S. businesses involved in the domestic extraction of critical minerals and the development of su...

Index of Posts (Linked)