Saturday, September 2, 2023

The Two Competing Paradigms of Environmental Philosophy that Undergird Environmental Law and Policy: The Harm-Benefit Feasibility Approach and the Precautionary Principle Approach

 

     This post is a light revision of a section of Chapter 2 of my 2021 book: Sensible Decarbonization: Regulation, Risk, and Relative Benefits in Different Approaches to Energy Use, Climate Policy, and Environmental Impact. As an easy way to compare and contrast, I assert that U.S. environmental law and policy are based more on the harm-benefit feasibility approach and E.U. environmental law and policy favor the Precautionary Principle. The differences in the two approaches are based mainly on levels of risk, both real and perceived and how that risk is mitigated. The contrasts can be seen in policies related to energy, bioengineering, and technology. Most research and prescriptions under the heading of ‘bioethics’ have proceeded from the assumption that the Precautionary Principle was somehow the natural intuitive way to proceed since, on the surface, it seems logical. This stems from the basically sensible idea of avoiding what can cause harm. However, if something that can cause harm can also be beneficial, we need to compare the potential harms and potential benefits. We also need to determine whether the level of harm is acceptable to receive the benefits. That is the basis of the harm-benefit approach. The harm-benefit approach is basically a cost-benefit approach and derives from cost-benefit analysis, or benefit-cost analysis, which is commonly applied to economic and environmental policy choices. It also considers feasibility analysis.

 

The Harm-Benefit Feasibility Approach

 

     The harm-benefit feasibility approach is akin to William James’ pragmatic method. According to legal scholar Cass Sunstein baselines are important to all legal arguments.  This is true in environmental law and possibly in most social, political, environmental, and legal issues. At question is where to put the line between what is acceptable and what is unacceptable. Legal limits, speed limits, emissions limits, and the EPA drinking water limits for contaminants are all examples. A regulation is quite often simply that line. In other examples, it is known as the “safety bar.” Sunstein is a major proponent of a cost-benefit approach utilizing cost-benefit analysis in evaluating risk. His 2018 book The Cost-Benefit Revolution is a detailed advocation of the analysis that undergirds the approach which he says is in some form or another “indispensable at arriving at sensible outcomes.” He says an unspoken principle of many public officials is: “No action may be taken unless the benefits justify the costs.” That includes regulatory actions. It must be shown that there is a benefit to such actions that justify the costs. 

     David L. Weimer, in his 2017 book Behavioral Economics for Cost-Benefit Analysis defines cost-benefit analysis as “a protocol for systematically assessing the economic efficiency of alternatives to current policy. It provides principles and conventions for monetizing the benefits and the costs of proposed policies relative to current policy for society as a whole. Its prediction of net benefits, the difference between benefits and costs, serves as a metric for economic efficiency.” You will notice that Weimer’s definition emphasizes the cost and benefits of changing the rules from what they are currently, so it is a comparison to the status quo. Cost-benefit analysis involves giving standardized values for human lives ($10 million per life currently in wealthy developed countries) and other human well-being metrics. While many people find the idea of putting a monetary value on human lives unsettling or even repugnant, the idea is to derive a statistical value of human lives, which is a value people are generally willing to accept. The other metric to derive a value from is willingness to pay. We know that people will die in traffic accidents, and we can reduce those deaths somewhat through stricter rules but what are people willing to accept in terms of speed limits and safety features and what will the added safety features of stricter rules cost? In some sense the values derive from what we are used to, the level of safety to which we are accustomed. The general harm-benefit approach I am featuring here does not require a cost-benefit analysis in great detail, simply a general analysis of benefits vs. costs. We are willing to accept some level of risk and willing to pay for some level of safety, to a point. How much we are willing to pay or willing to accept can vary by how much disposable income we have. People with more money are willing to pay more for things. If speed limits were doubled there would likely be more accidents and that level of risk would become unacceptable to most people. If speed limits were cut in half the risks would be quite acceptable but people would not be happy to pay in terms of longer commutes. Cost-benefit analysis also seeks to standardize valuations of variables along the spectrum of net cost and net benefit. A downside of cost-benefit analysis is that it could have high margins of error if valuations are not accurate and lead to overreaction or underreaction. An advantage is that if new information becomes available about risks the valuations can be adjusted or refined. Willingness to pay is important, says Sunstein, because it gives a kind of limit of what we can expect from the poorest. Most regulations, he says, are distributed in such a way that the poor pay a higher percentage of their income for them. Thus, in the rare circumstance when the wealthy will bear the financial brunt of a regulation, it is easier to approve it. Weimer also points out that cost-benefit analysis is rarely, if ever, the sole basis for making a rule but is rather “a protocol for assessing the relative efficiency of alternatives within the context of a multi-goal analysis.”  

 

 

Regulatory Impact Analysis

 

     Sunstein points out an executive order by Ronald Reagan that requires cost and benefits to be weighed, monetary or not, determination of who is benefited and who could be harmed, a regulatory impact analysis (RIA), and oversight and approval from the Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs (OIRA) within the Office of Management and Budget (OMB). This particular executive order, says Sunstein, was a victory for technocrats, giving more rule-making power to technical experts. The rule was designed, he thinks, to limit the role of “interest groups, anecdotes, institutions, and symbols,” or what he calls expressive regulation. Another reason it was designed was to slow down more new regulations as Reagan was known to favor less regulation and avoiding overregulation, which he believed was a major obstacle to economic growth. The order also served to keep federal agencies from developing their own agendas. Sunstein first worked at the Department of Justice in the Reagan administration and later became administrator of the OIRA in the Obama administration. He traces the cost-benefit requirement through that Reagan executive order that was left unaltered by George H.W. Bush, tweaked by Clinton to include distributive impacts (impacts that may be more or less on certain groups and economic classes), kept intact by George W. Bush even though many thought he would un-tweak the distributive impacts part, then cemented by Obama to include a requirement for retrospective analysis of past rules to see if they were still applicable, and an addition of human dignity as a value to consider.  I think the retrospective analysis of regulations to determine if they are working as designed in continually changing times is important. One example, although not an environmental law, might be the Jones Act, or Merchant Marine Act of 1920, or more specifically Section 27 of the act, which requires American-built, registered, and owned ships, where 75% of the crew needs to be American, in order to move goods between American ports. The rule was a response to World War I. Estimated costs to the U.S. economy are about $64 billion per year. Ultimately it is a protectionist law that is not in line with free markets and free trade.  Non-American ships that are better equipped to contain oil spills or provide relief efforts for hurricanes have been turned away due to the act. After 2017’s Hurricane Maria in Puerto Rico the US Dept. of Energy suggested that they use U.S. LNG to rebuild its damaged electrical system, but how could they? Puerto Rico imports only 1% of its LNG from the U.S. due to the expense of shipping even though U.S. LNG is cheaper than the LNG they import from Trinidad. Getting U.S. LNG in addition to that from Trinidad could help them continue to decarbonize away from fuel oil. In 2019 they requested a 10-year waiver of the Jones Act.  Some have described the effects of the Jones Act as an effective 7% tax on imports from the US to the US! Puerto Rico requested a waiver to the Jones Act after Hurricane Maria to get aid and U.S. LNG delivered but it was not granted. Ultimately, the act does not do what it was intended to do – support U.S. military shipbuilders. Many are now advocating for the repeal of the act or at least Section 27 of the Jones Act. 

     Recently (late 2020), the Center for Progressive Reform (CPR) outlined a plan “Beyond 12866” referring to a Clinton tweak to the OIRA in order to give less authority to OIRA or even abolish the OIRA, which was created by the Carter administration. These progressives don’t like that cost-benefit analysis is being applied to regulations and that there is executive branch oversight of the potential impacts of regulations. Others point out that it would be a bad idea to gut an office that has had remarkable bipartisan support over the years and performs necessary oversight. CPR claims that its “climate agenda” and climate policy are ill-suited to cost-benefit analysis. Apparently, they think the climate issue is too important to be subject to oversight and analysis of policy impacts. The then head of the OIRA, Paul Ray, put out a memo reflecting the Trump administration’s desire to stop enforcement of environmental regulations during the pandemic to aid economic recovery. Regulatory enforcement had already been way down since Trump took office. In January 2020 the Office of Management and Budget (OMB), under which the OIRA falls, issued a request for information on ways to rein in enforcement, describing an “oversized, aggressive bureaucratic state that for decades had inflicted undue penalties on ordinary Americans.” I’m not sure if that is the case. We obviously need regulatory enforcement, but we probably don’t need “undue penalties.” We do need penalties to be sufficient so that it doesn’t become easier for companies to just risk and pay fines rather than avoid their causes.

      Sunstein compares cost effects and welfare effects, net cost, and net welfare. He notes that an Obama executive order expands on Clinton’s “distributive impacts.” The order says that regulations can be justified on distributive grounds when they disproportionately benefit the poor so that priority is given to the most disadvantaged, an idea Sunstein calls prioritarianism. He also acknowledges that welfare benefits, whether prioritarian or overall utilitarian, trump purely cost-benefit analysis conclusions.      

     The cost-benefit approach and cost-benefit analysis are often imprecise. Values for each benefit and each cost are assigned on the basis of what we know, but the uncertainties are often considerable. It’s an attempt to quantify what is qualitative, and disagreements are often about the values assigned.  Predicting environmental impacts is often difficult, particularly long-term, and future impacts. In most cost-benefit analyses concerned with environmental law, there is higher value assigned to immediate impacts and lesser value assigned to future impacts, unless it can clearly be demonstrated that future impacts would be significantly more damaging. The cost-benefit approach is one with so-called trade-offs. Where we tend to put those boundaries may inform or influence our position on the left-right political spectrum. I think that it is important in addressing environmental issues to avoid the extremes simply because the further to the left or to the right one goes – either way, generally speaking – the further one gets imbued with ideology. Ideology is rarely helpful in solving problems. The socialist progressivist ideology that capitalism is inherently bad is one example. Another is the market fundamentalist libertarian ideology that says all regulation is bad. Moderates moderate between extremes. Extremists tend to hold more entrenched views. Of course, the center moves around from right to left or vice versa but usually not drastically. It varies according to place as well.

     Sunstein notes that there is little enthusiasm for cost-benefit analysis for two reasons. It is counterintuitive and putting number values on human lives just seems nefarious to many people. However, those may also be strengths of cost-benefit analysis. Evaluating risk with intuition is often dead wrong as we may discard logic for emotional reactions that are built-in to our neurobiology and lead often to behavioral biases. While putting monetary value on human lives may seem crass, it allows for comparisons and for consistent estimation of costs and benefits. Technocrats tend to favor cost-benefit analysis, but populists tend to favor what’s popular and available due to certain current events. Popularity and availability, usually through the media, can lead many people to mis-evaluate risk, in most cases to see something as more dangerous than it really is, but the opposite can happen as well, seeing something as less dangerous than it really is. Cost-benefit analysis can limit the influence of popularity and availability by scrutinizing public demands for regulation or deregulation. It can correct cognitive errors about risk.

 

 

Nudging and Libertarian Paternalism

 

     Sunstein also advocates for something called nudging in some public policies. This is a kind of behavioral economics that directs people to make health and safety decisions that are in their best interests by nudging them in that direction so that they do not make intuitive decisions that run counter to those interests. In these scenarios, we may be nudged into more long-term thinking, nudged into not being unrealistically optimistic or unrealistically pessimistic. This nudging has been referred to as a form of libertarian paternalism, which differs considerably from other kinds of paternalism in environmental debates, which often seek to eliminate risk by banning causes of risk altogether and have been associated with government overreach. Libertarian paternalism seeks to nudge people to avoid serious judgment errors but also to preserve freedom of choice. One might see the societal nudges to reduce one’s carbon footprint as a kind of social example. Indeed, any kind of regulation can be seen as a kind of enforced nudging, where choosing not to comply results in penalties. He thinks government-imposed nudging in some manner is inevitable and will happen, especially through choice architecture, which refers to setting up choice structures in such a way that we have choices but those are limited in some way to avoid the intuitions known to increase dangers, making us have to work harder to be less safe. Opt-in or opt-out clauses are examples.  Currently, we are seeing such opt-in, opt-out choice architecture in decisions about buying clean electricity.

     Dan Ariely in his 2008 book on behavioral economics Predictably Irrational: The Hidden Forces That Shape Our Decisions noted that people often make irrational decisions that are not in their own best interests and those irrational decisions often follow predictable patterns.  People are susceptible to biases, manipulative sales techniques, and other forms of influence or nudging from our social networks. Humans value autonomy and the right to make their own choices. Especially in America, we don’t want the government making choices for us. Philosopher Sarah Conly argued in her 2012 book Against Autonomy: Justifying Coercive Paternalism that making laws to protect people against their own bad decisions is justifiable. She favors bans on cigarettes, trans-fats, big portion sizes in restaurants, not saving enough money, and accruing too much debt.  While such ideas might seem attractive in terms of desired results, there is no doubt they would be highly unpopular, and any politician associated with them would be deemed suicidal. The idea of government-induced nudging is a bit controversial, and I am unsure about its applicability in some spheres. There is also perhaps some overlap with other policies. For instance, in subsidizing electric vehicles, solar panels, or other green technologies, governments can be seen as nudging people to buy things that produce less carbon emissions and less pollution. If the nudge was too strong, with the government making green technologies far cheaper than non-green ones, then people would buy them as a default and the government would likely run out of money for such programs. Some have even suggested that so-called “big nudging” is a potential threat to democracy, that it is a form of epistocracy, or rule by experts. Others, reaching back to Plato’s Republic, think that rule by experts, rather than rule by the majority of a less-informed public, is the best way to go. For topics like environmental protection and climate change, the progressive left is supportive of big nudging, but when they were sufficiently herded together without non-progressives in the Occupy Wall Street movement, they were all about “direct democracy.” Realistically, we need influence from both experts and the public. Ideally, the public would have some real and unbiased knowledge of the issues, which is often unfortunately not the case. People value both personal autonomy and expertise. We need to have a say, but direct democracy is rarely applicable, aside from elections. People generally don’t want social control by technocratic experts. However, most of us also don’t want highly biased people to dominate the political dialogue when given the chance as often seems to happen.

 

 

Reforming Cost-Benefit Analysis and Considering Co-Benefits

 

     Sunstein suggests four reforms of cost-benefit analysis, some already in place. First is a notice-and-comment period in order to get public input, especially input from those who might be affected by a new regulation. It is a good idea in principle. Unfortunately, in the permitting realm public input mechanisms like comment periods and public hearings have become the targets of activists, which upend the spirit of the idea by turning it into opportunities to protest, chant slogans at public hearings, and flood commentary with precautionary objections. Second is retrospective analysis of rules to be started immediately after a rule is implemented in order to determine its effects. Third is careful experimentation with preference given to randomized controlled trials as feasible. Fourth is measure-and-react which is also a kind of experimentation to gather information by implementing something in a limited fashion to see its effect.

     In May 2019 EPA administrator Andrew Wheeler outlined a plan to reform cost-benefit analysis at the EPA with the goal of making it more uniform and consistent across different agency branches. The goal was to eliminate unnecessary regulatory burdens as outlined in Trump’s Executive Order 13777. Another goal was simply to avoid rules that offer marginal benefits at great cost. Specifically, the directive addressed Clean Air Act regulations. The proposed rule is aimed at “Increasing Consistency and Transparency in Considering Benefits and Costs in the Clean Air Act Rulemaking Process.” Cass Sunstein praised Wheeler’s directive as an “important memorandum that makes terrific sense.” A regulatory impact analysis of the 2012 MATS (mercury and air toxics) rule directed at coal and oil power plants to ratchet up targets revealed that cost would be nearly $10 billion but the reduction in air toxics benefits would only be $4-6 million. Clearly, there was a regulatory burden to be carried by these plant owners. The rule was implemented anyway. That may not be the best example since there are clear economic alternatives to coal and oil power plants and solid reasonable arguments for replacing them with cleaner energy sources. Even so, Wheeler’s cost-benefit reform plan does address situations where the rules may cause more harm to the economy than good to its citizens. Critics of the reform say it restricts the Clean Air Act, likely the environmental regulation that has saved the most lives, and that it will make it harder in the future to implement air pollution rules. Since no one is currently building nor planning to build new oil or coal-fired plants and with the retirement of many and many more to come, the cleaner air as a result offsets more stringent rules and ratcheting up of rules as implemented. However, if I lived amidst poor air quality and had health problems that poor air quality could make worse, I might think differently since air quality is mostly a local issue. The proposal suggests not including co-benefits in the cost-benefit analysis but putting them in a separate document. Co-benefits are indirect benefits, added benefits, or ancillary benefits. Wheeler argued that co-benefits should not be used to justify a rule but should be available to be considered. The bottom line is that the change does not really amount to much. It is more a shifting of numbers and semantics. While it may help keep some polluters from more stringent regulations, it does not seem likely to spur any new unmitigated air pollution or rollbacks. There is some concern by environmentalists that the new rule could create obstacles to the Biden administration's climate actions by setting up a framework for legal challenges, but I don’t see that as a big issue. There likely will be legal challenges but that is another reason negotiation will be needed and overarching executive action will be curbed. It is sensible that indirect co-benefits be considered, but also sensible that they be considered separately from targeted benefits. Biden will have to spend considerable time and energy reversing Trump’s rollbacks.    


 

Feasibility Analysis: Can We Do It? Is It

Cost-Effective? What are the

Regulatory Costs? Is it Realistic?


     In the realms where humans and the rest of nature overlap, there seem to be four types of relevant feasibility: technical feasibility, economic feasibility, regulatory feasibility, and political feasibility. Technical feasibility is not just whether it can be done but whether it can be done effectively and to a degree that it will meet certain goals. Technical feasibility grades into economic feasibility so as more factors are considered more expense must be considered. We need to know whether it can be done at a reasonable cost. Regulatory feasibility is the third type where we need to know what the potential environmental impacts are, what are the technical specifications and economics of mitigating the harms they may cause, and how will they be determined, limited if applicable, and enforced. Regulatory impact analysis helps to determine regulatory feasibility. Political feasibility is simply the likelihood of something being adopted in the current political environment. Advocates of accelerated decarbonization talk about mustering the political will to put all of our eggs in the decarbonization basket. However, that is often quite unfeasible in the current divisive political environment where policy positions tend to be entrenched. We need to be realistic.

     Daniel Farber, in Eco-Pragmatism, explores aspects of feasibility analysis. He says that feasibility analysis tends toward presumptions that favor control while cost-benefit analysis tends to balance out such presumptions. Thus, advocating for maximum feasible regulation is often not a sound or fair approach since over-regulation might be quite feasible and still unnecessarily penalize corporations, ratepayers, and taxpayers. Calls for maximum feasible regulation may seem plausible but are often absolutist. We cannot eliminate all risks. A course of action may be quite feasible but unfair. Farber also suggests that feasibility analysis may hide trade-offs, making them implicit while cost-benefit analysis is an effort to keep trade-offs explicit. Cost-benefit analysis suffers from intangible value judgments like the statistical value of a human life, so it can be quite imprecise, but mortality is usually not the only risk. He sees feasibility analysis and cost-benefit analysis as competing frameworks that both have flaws but also notes that both can have roles in decision-making:

 

The conflict between cost-benefit analysis and feasibility analysis is more subtle than one might expect. Neither can be considered illegitimate in principle. Neither guarantees a firm answer, right or wrong. Both provide frameworks, and the choice of the right framework must be a pragmatic one. We must ask what framework works best – best in terms of the limits on available information, best in terms of political fairness and accountability, and, most important, best in term of capturing our society’s fullest understanding of the values at stake. Selection of a particular method of analysis may not force us to a particular conclusion, but it may at least give us a strong nudge in one direction.”

 

     Examples of feasible regulations include the reduction of methane leakage from oil and natural gas facilities. There are costs to comply with reductions but there are also benefits to the companies like capturing more product to sell and improving their public relations by addressing the problem. There is also the original goal of the regulation, the climate benefit, and often the lesser benefit of reducing local ground-level ozone since in some cases volatile organic compounds are captured as well. While some companies would rather not have to comply, others have stated that they are planning to comply with reductions whether they are required to or not. Since state and federal rules are likely to become more similar anyway, the focus on leak detection and repair will continue.  Another example is efficiency investments which are often technologically feasible but not always economically feasible.  Another example is air pollution abatement at power plants in the US. When power plants were forced to comply with new laws by installing scrubbers the plant owners complained that the costs would be too high. It turned out that the costs were less than predicted and the reduction in pollutants was significant and deemed successful. There, compliance turned out to be more feasible than the plant owners thought it would be. Compliance costs are usually higher, closer to when a rule is implemented. As compliance technology costs drop due to equipment and processes that become cheaper to make and install as they mature, those cost savings are passed on to the buyers. 


The Precautionary Principle Approach

 


     A second approach is embodied by the precautionary principle which argues that activities and technologies should be deemed unacceptable if there is some possibility that they will cause harm. The so-called Wingspread Declaration (Raffensperger and Tickner 1999) states that:

 

 “When an activity raises threats of harm to human health or the environment, precautionary measures should be taken even if some cause-and-effect relationships are not established scientifically. In this context, the proponent of an activity, rather than the public, should bear the burden of proof.” 

     According to Indur Goklany’s 2001 book The Precautionary Principle: A Critical Appraisal of Environmental Risk Assessment, the origin of the principle may be from German bureaucrats in 1965 or in the 1970s from the German principle of Vorsorgeprinzip, meaning foresight or precaution.  Its first use in an environmental forum context may have been in 1982 in the United Nations World Charter for Nature in the statement: when “potential adverse effects {of activities likely to pose significant risks to nature} are not fully understood, the activities should not proceed.” By the 1992 UN Conference on Environment and Development in Rio de Janeiro the use of the principle had become ubiquitous. Other forums, mostly UN groups, were vague and mentioned things like taking precautionary measures or a precautionary approach. In January 2000, the Cartagena Protocol on the Biosafety to the Convention on Biological Diversity repeatedly invoked the precautionary principle as a basis for assessing risks and making decisions about genetically modified organisms (GMOs). Since the U.S. also signed and ratified the Rio Declaration, some say we too are bound to follow the precautionary principle. Others say it was just an acknowledgment that we would exercise some caution in our endeavors. The declaration stated:

 

In order to protect the environment, the precautionary approach shall be widely applied by States according to their capabilities. Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost-effective measures to prevent environmental degradation.”

 

      The precautionary principle is certainly vaguer than the cost-benefit approach in that it fails to even consider benefits. Potentially, such a policy position can also slow and stifle technological progress toward reducing risks, thus, defeating its very purpose. Yet questions remain: How much harm? What level of cost should trigger that unacceptability? Thus, in the precautionary principle one can argue that the conclusion precedes the investigation, the conclusion being to deem the activity or technology unacceptable. Perhaps it should be called the pre-conclusionary principle. Critics argue that the so-called David Gee interpretation of the precautionary principle is a presumption of guilt. Gee was a leader in the European Environment Agency (EEA). Before that, he headed up the radical environmental group Friends of the Earth. In contemporary law, the notion of ‘innocent until proven guilty’ is enshrined. The Gee interpretation of the precautionary principle and what have been called absolutist interpretations of it, flip that around so that guilt is the presumption. Prove it is safe and you can get permission to do it. Gee wanted to apply the principle for RF exposure from mobile phones in the 2000s which may have slowed the technology considerably.  Prove safe by what standard? In aphorism one might say ‘erring on the side of caution’ but where does that side begin? Where does one put that baseline, that safety bar? According to the blogger Riskmonger in the article The Poison of Precaution: The Anti-Science Mindset, that safety bar is often set so high by precaution advocates that all technologies that they question will fail to meet the safety and certainty requirements. This blogger and Matt Ridley both argue that the EU’s general adoption of the precautionary approach as defined by Gee, with the burden of proof on the technology developers, is basically an anti-science mindset that leads to banning or denying technologies with potential net benefits, some of which could be highly beneficial.

     As an exercise, one might reverse the Wingspread declaration of the precautionary principle to say: “When an activity raises possible threats of harm to human health or the environment, precautionary measures should not be taken until cause-and-effect relationships are established scientifically.” This simply shifts the burden of proof onto those who would limit new technologies and processes from those who would proliferate them, which is probably an improvement in most cases. It is closer to Adam Thierer’s idea of “permissionless innovation.”  However, that might make it harder in some cases to get actual needed regulations accepted. It would be another static principle rather than a more dynamic process for evaluating risk. I do agree with Thierer that the highest burden should fall on those who seek to limit technologies to prove they are unsafe, at least to a point. I would argue for permissionless but cautious innovation. We can be cautious without being pre-emptive. As new and unforeseen safety and environmental impact issues arise, we can regulate them then, but we can also at some level anticipate those issues and if possible, begin to regulate them before they cause considerable problems. ‘Permissionless but cautious’ implies a shared burden of proof so rather than being more of a reverse precautionary principle like permissionless innovation, the adding of caution shifts some of the burden of proof onto to makers and doers of the technology, but still keeps a high degree of permissibility and most often keeps permissibility as the default.

     Thierer examines the precautionary principle in the article entitled: How Many Lives Are Lost Due to the Precautionary Principle? This article offers several good reasons why the principle is unfair, unscientific, and stifles innovation. Two main case examples are given. One is the golden rice example where anti-GMO activists were able to delay the launch of this life-saving food by 10 years in the interest of precaution, bogus precaution, say many. This bogus precaution extends to the many situations where genetic engineering and now CRISPR can improve and extend lives and livelihoods. The second case example is that of the post-Fukushima shutdown of nuclear plants that led to much higher electricity rates in Japan when nuclear was replaced by coal and gas plants, both at high fuel prices at the time. More people in Japan died of cold that winter and poorer air quality likely contributed to health problems and shortened lifespans. The same argument could be used for moving away from nuclear in the past due to what some describe as overblown safety concerns. Arguably, in these cases, the preventative, precautionary actions did more harm than good. Thierer argues convincingly that trial-and-error progress has always been a net beneficial feature of innovation. He writes: “Risk analysts and legal scholars have also criticized the precautionary principle because they argue it “lacks a firm foundation” and is “literally incoherent.” They argue the principle is in essence, a non-principle because it fails to specify a clear standard by which to judge which risks are most serious and worthy of preemptive control.”

    Thierer goes on to argue that the precautionary principle shows a clear preference for stasis, for the status quo. He mentions the work of political scientist Aaron Wildavsky and his 1988 book Searching for Safety which stresses the importance of trials (experiments) and trial-and-error as a way of evaluating risk and the dangers of trial-without-error which is the basic precautionary approach. Trials and experiments give us insights into how to reduce risk, and without them, there is far less chance of understanding the issues and risks. We may have an innate preference for stasis suggests new research on the endowment effect, our documented preference to keep what we have rather than trade it. Research at Vanderbilt University suggests that people indeed do over-value what they already have, especially if the product can aid survival or reproduction, or is perceived to aid survival or reproduction. We know from previous research that other primates show a distinct preference for what they have, a strong endowment effect, especially concerning food or tools that can access food, obvious survival items.

     As mentioned, we have direct evidence of the failure of applying the precautionary principle. The banning of genetically engineered crops has arguably resulted in significant harm, possibly millions of deaths and cases of blindness due to Vitamin A deficiency that could have been prevented by earlier adoption of genetically engineered Golden Rice. Another example of very real dangers is the past potential of banned DDT to prevent millions of deaths of children and adults from malaria by careful and controlled application. In 2000 malaria was causing about 1 million annual deaths. DDT probably saved millions of lives, but it also entered the ecosystem, killed raptors, and likely shortened lives of other animals and possibly some humans through cancer. However, almost all of the damage was done due to agricultural applications and almost none was due to controlled indoor application to stop mosquitoes, which is a life-saving application. In recent years, other pesticides carefully applied, and bed netting have been successful in reducing malaria deaths by about half from 2000.

     Riskmonger goes into detail with the problems of EU precaution in another post where he points out seven failures of the principle in action: 1) creates distrust in science 2) promotes a non-scientific logic 3) leads to political irresponsibility 4) fosters catastrophic false positives 5) confuses hazard with risk management 6) leads to supply chain fear opportunism and 7) can be manipulated by industries offering alternatives. Creating distrust in science is concerning. These days we all encounter this distrust, especially regarding genetic engineering and vaccines and this distrust has consequences. The non-scientific logic is simply that risk is considered but benefit is ignored. By that logic, precaution is never wrong even when it denies benefits that outweigh the risks. Precaution can be politically irresponsible in that the consequences of precautionary policy are not considered. False positives are simply cases where precaution ends up being detrimental. Confusing hazard with risk means using precaution as uncertainty management rather than risk management. It is simply avoiding risks rather than managing them. Supply chain opportunism means that if certain products, components, or practices are delayed or discouraged due to precaution, then alternatives will be found to replace them, often less effective and sometimes more damaging. Due to investments in those alternatives, however, they will often be kept even after the original was deemed safe. Industries producing alternatives can benefit from precaution and so are likely to promote precaution for their own benefit. When Elon Musk said it’s time to abandon fossil fuels for clean energy tech, he had a profit motivation for doing so. He has since backtracked and acknowledged that we need fossil fuels.

     In many places genetically engineered crops are winning out, but there is still quite a bit of resistance by groups like Greenpeace, even after such crops have been consumed regularly by humans and animals for more than two decades without incident or any demonstrable harm. The evidence is overwhelming and yet a dwindling minority still has significant sway. That, I think, shows a weakness in the precautionary principle, that the pre-conclusion toward unacceptability can remain for a long time, even in the face of overwhelming evidence. Perhaps if there was a retrospective analysis like Obama ordered for cost-benefit analysis, then the principle could be overridden in places where it is prevalent. But that rarely happens and when it does it can be many years later. This is perhaps one way the precautionary principle can be authoritarian. Another quasi-example involves regional bans on fracking. The fracking moratorium in the state of New York is midway into its second decade, there is no end in sight, and it has been enshrined as a permanent ban that is likely to remain. The stated rationale for the moratorium was to study it more to determine its potential harm. Despite numerous widespread studies in neighboring Pennsylvania where it has been occurring for the past 17 years showing that fracking does not cause significant water contamination nor concerning air quality issues, it is quite unlikely to be allowed any time soon, if ever. New York may be a special case where there is probably a majority of constituents that favor the ban, whether they are correctly informed or not. There, a major factor is likely NIMBYism and the nuisance aspect of the industry, things like noise, lights, and truck traffic, that is a major issue. Yet it’s still another example where there is no foreseeable move to reverse the pre-conclusion despite significant new information that contradicts it.

     Matt Ridley argues in his blog essay The EU’s Absurd Risk Aversion Stifles New Ideas, that the EU’s dependence on the precautionary principle puts it at odds with much of the world’s scientific standards as exemplified by the numerous disputes it has with the World Trade Organization. At issue are tariffs imposed on foreign grains and produce, often Asian, due to things like pesticide residues. France and Germany are phasing out two of the least toxic pesticides, neonicotinoids and glyphosate, which most scientists consider mild. Ridley notes that glyphosate used with minimal tillage replaces plowing and offers significant economic and environmental benefits that far outweigh the risks of those pesticides. Minimum tillage has quite a few environmental benefits over plowing: retention of soil structure, moisture, and microbes, less soil erosion, improved carbon storage, and less greenhouse gas emissions. Glyphosate is deemed generally safe by nearly all scientific bodies but is considered probably carcinogenic by only one body in France, one that is often in close agreement with California Proposition 65 cancer warnings which do not consider exposure levels so things like coffee, some fruits, and alcohol must be labeled carcinogenic. Ridley says the result of these overblown regs is more plowing and worse pesticides like copper sulfate. The older and more imprecise technology of gamma-ray bombardment of seeds (mutagenesis) to cause crop mutations is approved but in comparison, precision technologies like genetic engineering and CRISPR are very highly regulated and rarely approved. There is no logical reason mutagenesis should be less dangerous than transgenic methods, but they are regulated far differently. The final result is net environmental degradation, he says. He also suggests that the EU is using the regs as a pretext to limit certain food imports and favor domestic sources.  Recently, anti-biotech groups in the EU, quite a powerful lobby there, just sent a letter calling for an EU-wide ban on gene-drive technology via CRISPR/CAS9 and the release of gene-drive organisms (GDO’s), saying it is incompatible with the European Commission’s proposed biodiversity protection strategy. The technology, say many scientists, can help eradicate deadly diseases. Those same orgs plan to back a global moratorium on GDOs at the next Conference of the Parties (COP 15) to the UN Convention on Biological Diversity, a moratorium that the European Parliament supports. I am not sure if the genetically altered mosquitos to prevent Zika virus are of this sort. The Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation is involved in research under their Target Malaria project to eliminate populations of malaria-carrying mosquitos in some places. Regarding the proposed moratorium German NGO member Mareike Imken stated that such a technology “contradicts the aim of biodiversity conservation and the precautionary principle, which is the basis for international and EU nature conservation law.” It seems it could be the basis for EU law but is it for international law, presumably the UN? She also noted “A global moratorium would give us the time to assess environmental and health risks, publicly evaluate and discuss this technology and to establish missing regulations and global decision-making mechanisms. In the meanwhile, no-one in the world should use this technology.”  How long would that “meanwhile” last? Interestingly, this would make a 3rd major way, after the global ban on DDT and the delays and banning of GMOs in many places, that the precautionary principle can easily do more harm than good, and the 2nd way it can prevent stopping the proliferation of malaria. Those who could benefit from Golden Rice, African-specific GMOs, and the slowing of Zika, Dengue Fever, or malaria might want to call it the death principle. 

     Below is a table I made of apparent features and orientations of the precautionary principle vs. a non-precautionary cost-benefit approach. The non-precautionary approach is something like Adam Thierer’s permissionless innovation.

 

 


 

Precautionary approach vs. non-precautionary harm-benefit approach utilizing cost-benefit analysis. Source: Author

 

 

A Precautionary Approach Inhibits Ingenuity and Innovation

     Ingenuity and innovation are the cornerstones of problem-solving and human betterment. Julian Simon championed this idea and showed that human ingenuity trumps precautionary approaches, over-regulation, and apocalyptic scenarios. He showed especially that the availability of resources can be vastly improved by human ingenuity by reducing costs through technology which increases recoverability.  American ingenuity spurred many useful energy technology changes: unlocking nuclear energy, the fracking revolution which is the main reason the US leads the world in decarbonization, the development of solar energy, and the development of modern battery technology, to name a few. Solar energy development was cradled by NASA, the Pentagon, and by the US offshore oil and gas industry which used up to 70% of solar panels in the 1970’s. Modern lithium battery technology was vastly improved by the work of Exxon scientist John Goodenough. Exxon was also the first commercial manufacturer of solar panels. Thus, American Big Oil R&D was a big factor in the development of renewable energy, and in the case of fracking, investment and technology implementation by independent American energy companies was the key.  

 


Is the Precautionary Principle Authoritarian?


     In many cases pre-emptive denial of technology suppresses freedom. There are many examples. If landowners in Pennsylvania are free to lease their land to natural gas companies to drill and frack wells but landowners in neighboring New York are not, then one might say the freedoms of some New Yorkers are being suppressed. One may argue that it’s also the other way around, that Pennsylvania landowners are forced to deal with the issues that this activity brings up: potential (but unlikely) water contamination, potential temporary air pollution due to diesel engines, noise, traffic, lights, and sediment and erosion from well pads and pipelines, but New Yorkers are freed from such issues. Another may counter that Pennsylvanians will reap economic benefits including jobs, wealthier landowners, more robust ancillary industries, healthier economies due to impact fees, and other taxes, and many contributions and donations by the companies to the local communities and environment.

     Another situation that could be interpreted as authoritarian is the community rights movement that seeks to pre-empt state laws through local ordinances. This has happened with a pro-environmental legal firm known as the Community Environmental Legal Defense Fund (CELDF) founded by Thomas Linzey. This legal group has sought to stop many things that have effects on local communities, including the building of big box stores like Walmart (which due to efficiency and tighter supply chains are much more environmentally friendly than the local shops they replace), operations that may create public nuisance like large hog farms (OK I tend to agree that these are problematic), waste incinerators (often designated environmentally friendly in European countries), applying toxic sewage sludge as fertilizer, and more often, oil and gas operations like well pads, injection wells, and pipelines. CELDF is part of the Democracy over Corporations movement which decries corporations having rights in community relations issues. They have sponsored many local ballot initiatives that seek to ban fracking, some in many successive years in some places, none of which have succeeded.  Does that mean democracy chooses corporations over people? No, it means that most people prefer to stick with state rules rather than let a vocal group of local activists make the rules. Even if they were to succeed the states have said that such local initiatives cannot pre-empt state laws, insinuating that they would likely be overturned.

 

 

References:

 

Farber, Daniel A., 1999. Eco-pragmatism: Making Environmental Decisions in an Uncertain World. University of Chicago Press.

 

Sunstein, Cass, August 28, 2018. The Cost-Benefit Revolution. The MIT Press.

 

Weimer, David L., 2017.  Behavioral Economics for Cost-Benefit Analysis: Benefit Validity When Sovereign Consumers Seem to Make Mistakes. Cambridge University Press

 

Ibid.

 

Sunstein, Cass, August 28, 2018. The Cost-Benefit Revolution. The MIT Press.

 

Is it Time to Repeal the Jones Act? (POLICYbrief) – by the Federalist Society, on youtube.com, Nov. 12, 2019

 

Puerto Rico’s LNG imports returned to pre-Hurricane Maria levels in late 2018. Energy Information Administration. Today In Energy. April 8, 2019. https://www.eia.gov/todayinenergy/detail.php?id=38972

 

Hoxie, Philip G., July 22, 2019. The Jones Act is a Lose-Lose for Puerto Rico and US LNG, American Enterprise Institute (blog).

 

Brugger, Kelsey, August 28, 2020. ‘Abolish OIRA’: Left hopes Biden would reform regs shop, in E&E News.

 

Brugger, Kelsey, Sept. 1, 2020. Reg chief to agencies: Rein in enforcement, in E&E News.

 

Sunstein, Cass, August 28, 2018. The Cost-Benefit Revolution. The MIT Press.

Sunstein, Cass, 2014. Why Nudge? The Politics of Libertarian Paternalism. Yale University Press.

 

Ariely, Dan, 2009. Predictably Irrational: The Hidden Forces That Shape Our Decisions. Imprint/Harper-Collins

 

 Conly, Sarah, 2012 Against Autonomy: Justifying Coercive Paternalism. Cambridge University Press.

 Tampio, Nicholas, October 18, 2017. Treat people as citizens. Aeon newsletter. https://aeon.co/essays/why-rule-by-the-people-is-better-than-rule-by-the-experts

 

Sunstein, Cass, August 28, 2018. The Cost-Benefit Revolution. The MIT Press.

 

Caso, Anthony T., August 12, 2020. Cost-benefit analysis rule critical to EPA’s future environmental regulations. The Washington Times. https://www.washingtontimes.com/news/2020/aug/12/cost-benefit-analysis-rule-critical-to-epas-future/

 

McLinko, Doug, October 15, 2020. Wheeler EPA Cost Benefit Reform a Bipartisan Success if Allowed to Be! Natural Gas Now. https://naturalgasnow.org/wheeler-epa-cost-benefit-reform-a-bipartisan-success-if-allowed-to-be/

 

Beitsch, Rebecca, June 4, 2020. New Trump air rule will limit future pollution regulations, critics say. https://thehill.com/policy/energy-environment/501225-new-trump-air-rule-will-limit-future-pollution-regulations-critics

 

Jaffe, Seth, June 8, 2019. EPA’s New Cost-Benefit Rule — Are Both Sides Misrepresenting What It Says? Foley Hoag LLP. Law and the Environment. https://www.lawandenvironment.com/2020/06/08/epas-new-cost-benefit-rule-are-both-sides-misrepresenting-what-it-says/

 

Hijazi, Jennifer, December 15, 2020. EPA cost-benefit rule could undermine Biden climate action. E&E News. https://www.eenews.net/stories/1063720663

 

The Precautionary Principle - The Wingspread Statement. https://www.asmalldoseoftoxicology.org/blog/2018/3/8/the-precautionary-principle-the-wingspread-statement

 

Goklany, Indur M., 2001, The Precautionary Principle: A Critical Appraisal of Environmental Risk Assessment. Cato Institute.

 

Joel Tickner – Lowell Center for Sustainable Production Carolyn Raffensperger – Science and Environmental Health Network and Nancy Myers, n.d., The Precautionary Principle in Action: A Handbook.

 

David Gee, n.d. EMF: Evaluating Evidence and Use of the Precautionary Principle. Science, Policy,

Innovation, EEA, Copenhagen. (Power Point presentation for a meeting organized by Health & Consumer Protection DG)

 

Riskmonger, June 4, 2019. The Poison of Precaution: The Anti-Science Mindset (blog post).

https://risk-monger.com/2019/06/04/the-poison-of-precaution/

 

Thierer, Adam, 2014, 2016. Permissionless Innovation: The Continuing Case for Comprehensive Technological Freedom. Mercatus Center at George Mason University.

 

Thierer, Adam, Nov. 4, 2019. How Many Lives Are Lost Due to the Precautionary Principle? – by Adam Thierer, in Human Progress. https://www.humanprogress.org/how-many-lives-are-lost-due-to-the-precautionary-principle/

 

Entzman, Liz, May 27, 2020. New research on ‘endowment effect’ points to evolutionary roots of cognitive biases. Vanderbilt University. https://news.vanderbilt.edu/2020/05/27/new-research-on-endowment-effect-points-to-evolutionary-roots-of-cognitive-biases/

 

The Risk-Monger, October 31, 2017. Seven Reasons the EU’s Use of the Precautionary Principle is Misguided. https://risk-monger.com/2017/10/31/seven-reasons-the-eus-use-of-the-precautionary-principle-is-misguided/

 

Ridley, Matt, Dec. 9, 2019. The EU’s Absurd Risk Aversion Stifles New Ideas. Blog. http://www.rationaloptimist.com/blog/eu-risk-aversion/

 

Foote, Natasha, July 3, 2020. NGOs Call for Moratorium on Controversial ‘Gene Drive Organisms’. EURACTIV. https://www.euractiv.com/section/health-consumers/news/ngos-call-for-moratorium-on-controversial-gene-drive-organisms/

 

Kaplan, Bryan, Sept. 30, 2015. What’s Libertarian about Betting, in Econlib.org. https://www.econlib.org/archives/2015/09/whats_libertari.html#:~:text=The%20Libertarian%20position%20is%20usually%20akin%20to%20a,being%20made%20under%20inflated%20probability%20of%20success%20expectations.

 

Simon, Julian, 1999. Hoodwinking the Nation. Transaction Publishers.

 

Stewart, Kent, May 3, 2020. Big Oil and Green Energy: A Long History of Collaboration, Recent Moves, and Allocating Capital as a Hedge Against Future Contraction in the Oil & Gas Industry. Blue Dragon Energy Blog. www.bluedragonenergy.blogspot.com/2020/05/big-oil-and-green-energy-long-history.html

 

Fletcher, Seth, 2011. Bottled Lightning: Superbatteries, Electric Cars, and the New Lithium Economy. Hill & Wang.

 

Linzey, Thomas, Nov. 13, 2015. Breaking a Fixed System: Corporations, Fracking, and the Community Rights Movement in Ohio – a talk by Thomas Linzey, founder of CELDF, in Athens, Ohio.

 

Stewart, Kent, Nov. 22, 2015. Risk Assessment: The Basis of the Debates about Fracking, Injection Wells, and Most Debates about Environmental Impact and Policy. Blue Dragon Energy Blog. http://bluedragonenergy.blogspot.com/2015/11/risk-assessment-basis-of-debates-about.html

No comments:

Post a Comment

     The SCORE Consortium is a group of U.S. businesses involved in the domestic extraction of critical minerals and the development of su...

Index of Posts (Linked)